Discussion about this post

User's avatar
Gordon Friesen's avatar

Again, the non-medical approach would address this. Although there would still be criteria, they would no longer specify which medical conditions are required to qualify.

***************************

Actually, in the jurisdictions that have taken the non-medical route, there are no criteria, other than capacity to choose. In fact, that is the whole point. The key examples are Switzerland and Germany.

German High Court decision February 26, 2020 https://www.bundesverfassungsgericht.de/SharedDocs/Pressemitteilungen/EN/2020/bvg20-012.html accessed Oct 28, 2023

Swiss criminal code art. 115 https://www.fedlex.admin.ch/eli/cc/54/757_781_799/en#art_115 accessed Nov 4, 2023

Best,

Gordon

Expand full comment
Josh Briscoe's avatar

One question that comes up for me in considering the rights-based discussion of this issue is how it leads to the formation of a particular culture. You can see this in some areas of the USA re: the Second Amendment: the culture is deeply pro-gun ownership. It's not just about the right, but flaunting guns, etc. There's a big debate in the USA about our society's relationship with guns.

When we consider this right to end of one's life, I worry about the judgments required to inform it. Your proposal would free it from medical authority and place more power in the hands of individuals, but cultures are the accumulation of individual behaviors and decisions. So, if enough people say, "I would never want to live like *that.* *That* is not a life worth living," then a culture eventually comes to devalue that life. You see this devaluing as people refer to severely cognitively impaired people as "vegetables," for example.

I'm also struck by David Velleman's dinner party analogy (https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/1479311/). He's having a dinner party and you're not invited, so you're not coming by default. No choice for you to make. If he invites you, though, you can choose to come or not to come, but the one thing you can no longer do, the one thing his offer has taken from you, is the possibility of not coming by default. There may be certain circumstances in which it would have been better for you not to come, but now that you have the choice, you must choose to go.

The offer of death, in Velleman's view, operates similarly. Most people don't wake up every day consciously deciding to live. They just live by default. Now here comes someone saying, "You know, you could kill yourself," or "We could euthanize you." The person can certainly decide to do so or not, but the one thing they can no longer do is live by default. That puts them in the precarious position of justifying, if only to themselves, their continued existence. "Hm, I'd never thought about that before. Why *is* my life worth living?" I don't see a way of overcoming this challenge. Once ending one's life is made a viable option (rather than one that's discouraged, even resisted), it changes the context of all of one's decisions and self-evaluations, even for those who weren't chomping at the bit to get it.

Expand full comment
6 more comments...

No posts